basic difference between canonical isomorphism and isomorphimsRings and isomorphismIsomorphism between...

What makes accurate emulation of old systems a difficult task?

How can Republicans who favour free markets, consistently express anger when they don't like the outcome of that choice?

a sore throat vs a strep throat vs strep throat

Is there really no use for MD5 anymore?

Mistake in years of experience in resume?

Can an Area of Effect spell cast outside a Prismatic Wall extend inside it?

Was Dennis Ritchie being too modest in this quote about C and Pascal?

As an international instructor, should I openly talk about my accent?

Can someone publish a story that happened to you?

Size of electromagnet needed to replicate Earth's magnetic field

How did Captain America manage to do this?

Why did C use the -> operator instead of reusing the . operator?

Map of water taps to fill bottles

Was there a Viking Exchange as well as a Columbian one?

How can I practically buy stocks?

What happened to Captain America in Endgame?

How much cash can I safely carry into the USA and avoid civil forfeiture?

Multiple options vs single option UI

How do I reattach a shelf to the wall when it ripped out of the wall?

Is the claim "Employers won't employ people with no 'social media presence'" realistic?

A ​Note ​on ​N!

How to fry ground beef so it is well-browned

A Paper Record is What I Hamper

Implications of cigar-shaped bodies having rings?



basic difference between canonical isomorphism and isomorphims


Rings and isomorphismIsomorphism between multiplicative and additive groups of realsIsomorphism between $mathbb{T}$ and $mathbb{R}^n/Gamma$?Isomorphism between $mathbb Q times C_2$ and $mathbb Q^*$Isomorphism between Fundamental Group and $mathbb Z$Isomorphism between $HK$ and $H⋊ K$Isomorphism between $Hom$ and $mathbb{Z}_n$Isomorphism between $bigwedge^k V$ and $bigwedge^{n-k} V^*$?Isomorphism between finite groupsFunctional equations and finding isomorphism between groups













7












$begingroup$


What is the basic difference between canonical isomorphism and isomorphims?



I need some basic analysis.



As far as I consider on canonical isomorphism means a similarity between two geometric object having same kind of configuration and structure.



While isomorphism means a map between two algebraic object or group or fields etc.



But I am not satisfied with my own analysis.



Can someone help me understanding these two definitions ?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    A canonical isomorphism is a "normal" isomorphism with the implication that it is somehow "easy" for the human mind to come with that isomorphism. For example, the canonical isomorphism between any object $G$ and $G$ (yes, two times) is the identity.
    $endgroup$
    – SK19
    21 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @SK19, In that case the identity map between $G$ to $G$ is also an isomorphism
    $endgroup$
    – M. A. SARKAR
    21 hours ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Usually people refer to an isomorphism as being canonical if it does not involve any artificial choices. Often this amounts to saying that the isomorphism is part of a natural transformation between certain functors, if you are familiar with this language.
    $endgroup$
    – asdq
    20 hours ago


















7












$begingroup$


What is the basic difference between canonical isomorphism and isomorphims?



I need some basic analysis.



As far as I consider on canonical isomorphism means a similarity between two geometric object having same kind of configuration and structure.



While isomorphism means a map between two algebraic object or group or fields etc.



But I am not satisfied with my own analysis.



Can someone help me understanding these two definitions ?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    A canonical isomorphism is a "normal" isomorphism with the implication that it is somehow "easy" for the human mind to come with that isomorphism. For example, the canonical isomorphism between any object $G$ and $G$ (yes, two times) is the identity.
    $endgroup$
    – SK19
    21 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @SK19, In that case the identity map between $G$ to $G$ is also an isomorphism
    $endgroup$
    – M. A. SARKAR
    21 hours ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Usually people refer to an isomorphism as being canonical if it does not involve any artificial choices. Often this amounts to saying that the isomorphism is part of a natural transformation between certain functors, if you are familiar with this language.
    $endgroup$
    – asdq
    20 hours ago
















7












7








7


1



$begingroup$


What is the basic difference between canonical isomorphism and isomorphims?



I need some basic analysis.



As far as I consider on canonical isomorphism means a similarity between two geometric object having same kind of configuration and structure.



While isomorphism means a map between two algebraic object or group or fields etc.



But I am not satisfied with my own analysis.



Can someone help me understanding these two definitions ?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




What is the basic difference between canonical isomorphism and isomorphims?



I need some basic analysis.



As far as I consider on canonical isomorphism means a similarity between two geometric object having same kind of configuration and structure.



While isomorphism means a map between two algebraic object or group or fields etc.



But I am not satisfied with my own analysis.



Can someone help me understanding these two definitions ?







group-isomorphism






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked 21 hours ago









M. A. SARKARM. A. SARKAR

1




1








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    A canonical isomorphism is a "normal" isomorphism with the implication that it is somehow "easy" for the human mind to come with that isomorphism. For example, the canonical isomorphism between any object $G$ and $G$ (yes, two times) is the identity.
    $endgroup$
    – SK19
    21 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @SK19, In that case the identity map between $G$ to $G$ is also an isomorphism
    $endgroup$
    – M. A. SARKAR
    21 hours ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Usually people refer to an isomorphism as being canonical if it does not involve any artificial choices. Often this amounts to saying that the isomorphism is part of a natural transformation between certain functors, if you are familiar with this language.
    $endgroup$
    – asdq
    20 hours ago
















  • 3




    $begingroup$
    A canonical isomorphism is a "normal" isomorphism with the implication that it is somehow "easy" for the human mind to come with that isomorphism. For example, the canonical isomorphism between any object $G$ and $G$ (yes, two times) is the identity.
    $endgroup$
    – SK19
    21 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @SK19, In that case the identity map between $G$ to $G$ is also an isomorphism
    $endgroup$
    – M. A. SARKAR
    21 hours ago






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Usually people refer to an isomorphism as being canonical if it does not involve any artificial choices. Often this amounts to saying that the isomorphism is part of a natural transformation between certain functors, if you are familiar with this language.
    $endgroup$
    – asdq
    20 hours ago










3




3




$begingroup$
A canonical isomorphism is a "normal" isomorphism with the implication that it is somehow "easy" for the human mind to come with that isomorphism. For example, the canonical isomorphism between any object $G$ and $G$ (yes, two times) is the identity.
$endgroup$
– SK19
21 hours ago




$begingroup$
A canonical isomorphism is a "normal" isomorphism with the implication that it is somehow "easy" for the human mind to come with that isomorphism. For example, the canonical isomorphism between any object $G$ and $G$ (yes, two times) is the identity.
$endgroup$
– SK19
21 hours ago












$begingroup$
@SK19, In that case the identity map between $G$ to $G$ is also an isomorphism
$endgroup$
– M. A. SARKAR
21 hours ago




$begingroup$
@SK19, In that case the identity map between $G$ to $G$ is also an isomorphism
$endgroup$
– M. A. SARKAR
21 hours ago




3




3




$begingroup$
Usually people refer to an isomorphism as being canonical if it does not involve any artificial choices. Often this amounts to saying that the isomorphism is part of a natural transformation between certain functors, if you are familiar with this language.
$endgroup$
– asdq
20 hours ago






$begingroup$
Usually people refer to an isomorphism as being canonical if it does not involve any artificial choices. Often this amounts to saying that the isomorphism is part of a natural transformation between certain functors, if you are familiar with this language.
$endgroup$
– asdq
20 hours ago












3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















10












$begingroup$

Great question. Canonical is more a term of art than a word with a strict mathematical definition. It's sometimes used as a synonym for “natural” or “obvious,” although natural is yet another idiom and obvious is in the eye of the beholder. You might think of it as meaning independent of any choices.



It sounds like you're in an abstract algebra class now, but hopefully this linear algebra example will make sense. Let $V$ be a vector space over $mathbb{R}$ of dimension $n$. By choosing a basis $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, $V$ is isomorphic to $mathbb{R}^n$. What is the isomorphism? It takes $vin V$, decomposes it into $alpha_1 v_1 + dots + alpha_n v_n$, and assigns to $v$ the $n$-tuple $(alpha_1,dots,alpha_n)$.



Through the isomorphism to $mathbb{R}^n$, all vector spaces of the same dimension are isomorphic to each other, but not for any good reason, and not in any natural way. The isomorphism depends on the choice of basis.



Let $V^*$ be the dual space to $V$, that is, the vector space of linear functions $V to mathbb{R}$. Once you choose a basis of $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, you can form a dual basis $(lambda_1,dots,lambda_n)$ of $V^*$, such that $lambda_i(v_j) = delta_{ij}$. So $V$ and $V^*$ are isomorphic, but not canonically so.



Now let $V^{**}$ be the dual space of $V^*$. Elements of $V^{**}$ are linear functions from $V^*$ to $mathbb{R}$. One way to create such a map is to select $v in V$ and send $lambda in V^*$ to $lambda(v)$. This association extends to a linear map
$$
f colon V to V^{**}, f(v)(lambda) = lambda(v)
$$

By a dimension count, this map has to be an isomorphism. And, we didn't have to choose a basis to create it. For this reason, we say that $V$ and $V^{**}$ are canonically isomorphic.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Or canonical as "given by definition", such as the projections $Atimes Bto A$ and $Atimes Bto B$, which are part of the definition of $times $ via universal property.(Note that by this have two distinct canonical maps $Atimes Ato A$!)
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    10 hours ago



















3












$begingroup$

I agree with @MatthewLeingang that this is an excellent question. A canonical isomorphism is one that comes along with the structures you are investigating, requiring no arbitrary choices. Here's another example from abstract algebra.



Whenever you have a surjective group homomorphism $sigma: G to H$ there is a natural isomorphism
$$
phi : G/(ker sigma) to H
$$

defined by setting $phi (C) = sigma(g)$ for any $g in C$. Here $C$ is a coset of the kernel of $sigma$ and the value of $phi$ is independent of the choice of $g in C$.



When $sigma$ is not surjective this defines a canonical injective homomorphism.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    I agree with your example, but could you say a sentence or two about what you see in it as being canonical? Why is that particular map the one to choose?
    $endgroup$
    – Santana Afton
    11 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    @SantanaAfton The map is an integral part of the definition of quotient (or cokernel), hence canonical (given $sigma$)
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    10 hours ago





















0












$begingroup$

Too much for a comment, but there some things I do not see mentioned in the existing answers and comments. "Natural" and "canonical" have related but somewhat different meanings in mathematics. This doesn't mean everyone uses them perfectly in accordance to those meanings. But this is a common usage. I'll start out with "natural" first, then bring in "canonical".



The term natural actually has a precise mathematical meaning, defined in Category theory. In fact, Category theory was originally invented to define what "natural" means. (The first step to studying something is to define it, and once you've defined "natural transformations", you can use them to define "natural" more broadly.)



An intuitive grasp of "natural" is that it means something is definable by the generic properties of objects in the theory under study, rather than by properties of the specific objects for which the thing is being defined.



As Matthew Leingang has discussed, finite dimensional real vector spaces are isomorphic to their dual spaces. But in order to have such an isomophism, we have to pick a basis for the vector space. The isomorphism requires something specific to this vector space in order to define it. But we don't require that to define this isomorphism $phi$ of a vector space with its second dual. We can define just from the definition of "dual of a real vector space": $$forall v in V, f in V^*, phi(v)(f) := f(v)$$
That is why $phi$ is "natural".



But note this weasel wording in the description above: "in the theory under study". This is why "natural" becomes a word of art, rather than of precision: most of the time, we don't bother to lay out the category that allows a precise definition of "natural". That is left to our audience to deduce. You see, a little tightening of the category under discussion will suddenly turn the unnatural into natural. In finite-dimensional linear algebra, $V$ is not naturally isomorphic to $V^*$. But in the theory of matrices, a column space is naturally isomorphic to a row space by transposing, even though the row space is natually isomorphic to the dual of the column space.



When someone calls something "natural", you have to figure out in what context they are speaking. And this is where "canonical" comes in. When we call something "canonical" when there is a familiar (and obvious) context where it is natural, but we are (usually) working in a broader context where it is not natural. For example, the canonical basis of $Bbb R^n$ is natural when discussing matrices and column spaces - so natural we don't even mention it, even though it underlies practically everything we do. But if we are considering $Bbb R^n$ as an example of a vector space, then it is not natural, but is defined by non-vector-space properties of $Bbb R^n$. So we use "canonical" to describe it instead.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$














    Your Answer








    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3203028%2fbasic-difference-between-canonical-isomorphism-and-isomorphims%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes








    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    10












    $begingroup$

    Great question. Canonical is more a term of art than a word with a strict mathematical definition. It's sometimes used as a synonym for “natural” or “obvious,” although natural is yet another idiom and obvious is in the eye of the beholder. You might think of it as meaning independent of any choices.



    It sounds like you're in an abstract algebra class now, but hopefully this linear algebra example will make sense. Let $V$ be a vector space over $mathbb{R}$ of dimension $n$. By choosing a basis $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, $V$ is isomorphic to $mathbb{R}^n$. What is the isomorphism? It takes $vin V$, decomposes it into $alpha_1 v_1 + dots + alpha_n v_n$, and assigns to $v$ the $n$-tuple $(alpha_1,dots,alpha_n)$.



    Through the isomorphism to $mathbb{R}^n$, all vector spaces of the same dimension are isomorphic to each other, but not for any good reason, and not in any natural way. The isomorphism depends on the choice of basis.



    Let $V^*$ be the dual space to $V$, that is, the vector space of linear functions $V to mathbb{R}$. Once you choose a basis of $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, you can form a dual basis $(lambda_1,dots,lambda_n)$ of $V^*$, such that $lambda_i(v_j) = delta_{ij}$. So $V$ and $V^*$ are isomorphic, but not canonically so.



    Now let $V^{**}$ be the dual space of $V^*$. Elements of $V^{**}$ are linear functions from $V^*$ to $mathbb{R}$. One way to create such a map is to select $v in V$ and send $lambda in V^*$ to $lambda(v)$. This association extends to a linear map
    $$
    f colon V to V^{**}, f(v)(lambda) = lambda(v)
    $$

    By a dimension count, this map has to be an isomorphism. And, we didn't have to choose a basis to create it. For this reason, we say that $V$ and $V^{**}$ are canonically isomorphic.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Or canonical as "given by definition", such as the projections $Atimes Bto A$ and $Atimes Bto B$, which are part of the definition of $times $ via universal property.(Note that by this have two distinct canonical maps $Atimes Ato A$!)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago
















    10












    $begingroup$

    Great question. Canonical is more a term of art than a word with a strict mathematical definition. It's sometimes used as a synonym for “natural” or “obvious,” although natural is yet another idiom and obvious is in the eye of the beholder. You might think of it as meaning independent of any choices.



    It sounds like you're in an abstract algebra class now, but hopefully this linear algebra example will make sense. Let $V$ be a vector space over $mathbb{R}$ of dimension $n$. By choosing a basis $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, $V$ is isomorphic to $mathbb{R}^n$. What is the isomorphism? It takes $vin V$, decomposes it into $alpha_1 v_1 + dots + alpha_n v_n$, and assigns to $v$ the $n$-tuple $(alpha_1,dots,alpha_n)$.



    Through the isomorphism to $mathbb{R}^n$, all vector spaces of the same dimension are isomorphic to each other, but not for any good reason, and not in any natural way. The isomorphism depends on the choice of basis.



    Let $V^*$ be the dual space to $V$, that is, the vector space of linear functions $V to mathbb{R}$. Once you choose a basis of $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, you can form a dual basis $(lambda_1,dots,lambda_n)$ of $V^*$, such that $lambda_i(v_j) = delta_{ij}$. So $V$ and $V^*$ are isomorphic, but not canonically so.



    Now let $V^{**}$ be the dual space of $V^*$. Elements of $V^{**}$ are linear functions from $V^*$ to $mathbb{R}$. One way to create such a map is to select $v in V$ and send $lambda in V^*$ to $lambda(v)$. This association extends to a linear map
    $$
    f colon V to V^{**}, f(v)(lambda) = lambda(v)
    $$

    By a dimension count, this map has to be an isomorphism. And, we didn't have to choose a basis to create it. For this reason, we say that $V$ and $V^{**}$ are canonically isomorphic.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Or canonical as "given by definition", such as the projections $Atimes Bto A$ and $Atimes Bto B$, which are part of the definition of $times $ via universal property.(Note that by this have two distinct canonical maps $Atimes Ato A$!)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago














    10












    10








    10





    $begingroup$

    Great question. Canonical is more a term of art than a word with a strict mathematical definition. It's sometimes used as a synonym for “natural” or “obvious,” although natural is yet another idiom and obvious is in the eye of the beholder. You might think of it as meaning independent of any choices.



    It sounds like you're in an abstract algebra class now, but hopefully this linear algebra example will make sense. Let $V$ be a vector space over $mathbb{R}$ of dimension $n$. By choosing a basis $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, $V$ is isomorphic to $mathbb{R}^n$. What is the isomorphism? It takes $vin V$, decomposes it into $alpha_1 v_1 + dots + alpha_n v_n$, and assigns to $v$ the $n$-tuple $(alpha_1,dots,alpha_n)$.



    Through the isomorphism to $mathbb{R}^n$, all vector spaces of the same dimension are isomorphic to each other, but not for any good reason, and not in any natural way. The isomorphism depends on the choice of basis.



    Let $V^*$ be the dual space to $V$, that is, the vector space of linear functions $V to mathbb{R}$. Once you choose a basis of $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, you can form a dual basis $(lambda_1,dots,lambda_n)$ of $V^*$, such that $lambda_i(v_j) = delta_{ij}$. So $V$ and $V^*$ are isomorphic, but not canonically so.



    Now let $V^{**}$ be the dual space of $V^*$. Elements of $V^{**}$ are linear functions from $V^*$ to $mathbb{R}$. One way to create such a map is to select $v in V$ and send $lambda in V^*$ to $lambda(v)$. This association extends to a linear map
    $$
    f colon V to V^{**}, f(v)(lambda) = lambda(v)
    $$

    By a dimension count, this map has to be an isomorphism. And, we didn't have to choose a basis to create it. For this reason, we say that $V$ and $V^{**}$ are canonically isomorphic.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    Great question. Canonical is more a term of art than a word with a strict mathematical definition. It's sometimes used as a synonym for “natural” or “obvious,” although natural is yet another idiom and obvious is in the eye of the beholder. You might think of it as meaning independent of any choices.



    It sounds like you're in an abstract algebra class now, but hopefully this linear algebra example will make sense. Let $V$ be a vector space over $mathbb{R}$ of dimension $n$. By choosing a basis $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, $V$ is isomorphic to $mathbb{R}^n$. What is the isomorphism? It takes $vin V$, decomposes it into $alpha_1 v_1 + dots + alpha_n v_n$, and assigns to $v$ the $n$-tuple $(alpha_1,dots,alpha_n)$.



    Through the isomorphism to $mathbb{R}^n$, all vector spaces of the same dimension are isomorphic to each other, but not for any good reason, and not in any natural way. The isomorphism depends on the choice of basis.



    Let $V^*$ be the dual space to $V$, that is, the vector space of linear functions $V to mathbb{R}$. Once you choose a basis of $(v_1,dots,v_n)$, you can form a dual basis $(lambda_1,dots,lambda_n)$ of $V^*$, such that $lambda_i(v_j) = delta_{ij}$. So $V$ and $V^*$ are isomorphic, but not canonically so.



    Now let $V^{**}$ be the dual space of $V^*$. Elements of $V^{**}$ are linear functions from $V^*$ to $mathbb{R}$. One way to create such a map is to select $v in V$ and send $lambda in V^*$ to $lambda(v)$. This association extends to a linear map
    $$
    f colon V to V^{**}, f(v)(lambda) = lambda(v)
    $$

    By a dimension count, this map has to be an isomorphism. And, we didn't have to choose a basis to create it. For this reason, we say that $V$ and $V^{**}$ are canonically isomorphic.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited 17 hours ago

























    answered 20 hours ago









    Matthew LeingangMatthew Leingang

    17k12345




    17k12345












    • $begingroup$
      Or canonical as "given by definition", such as the projections $Atimes Bto A$ and $Atimes Bto B$, which are part of the definition of $times $ via universal property.(Note that by this have two distinct canonical maps $Atimes Ato A$!)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago


















    • $begingroup$
      Or canonical as "given by definition", such as the projections $Atimes Bto A$ and $Atimes Bto B$, which are part of the definition of $times $ via universal property.(Note that by this have two distinct canonical maps $Atimes Ato A$!)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago
















    $begingroup$
    Or canonical as "given by definition", such as the projections $Atimes Bto A$ and $Atimes Bto B$, which are part of the definition of $times $ via universal property.(Note that by this have two distinct canonical maps $Atimes Ato A$!)
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    10 hours ago




    $begingroup$
    Or canonical as "given by definition", such as the projections $Atimes Bto A$ and $Atimes Bto B$, which are part of the definition of $times $ via universal property.(Note that by this have two distinct canonical maps $Atimes Ato A$!)
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    10 hours ago











    3












    $begingroup$

    I agree with @MatthewLeingang that this is an excellent question. A canonical isomorphism is one that comes along with the structures you are investigating, requiring no arbitrary choices. Here's another example from abstract algebra.



    Whenever you have a surjective group homomorphism $sigma: G to H$ there is a natural isomorphism
    $$
    phi : G/(ker sigma) to H
    $$

    defined by setting $phi (C) = sigma(g)$ for any $g in C$. Here $C$ is a coset of the kernel of $sigma$ and the value of $phi$ is independent of the choice of $g in C$.



    When $sigma$ is not surjective this defines a canonical injective homomorphism.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      I agree with your example, but could you say a sentence or two about what you see in it as being canonical? Why is that particular map the one to choose?
      $endgroup$
      – Santana Afton
      11 hours ago










    • $begingroup$
      @SantanaAfton The map is an integral part of the definition of quotient (or cokernel), hence canonical (given $sigma$)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago


















    3












    $begingroup$

    I agree with @MatthewLeingang that this is an excellent question. A canonical isomorphism is one that comes along with the structures you are investigating, requiring no arbitrary choices. Here's another example from abstract algebra.



    Whenever you have a surjective group homomorphism $sigma: G to H$ there is a natural isomorphism
    $$
    phi : G/(ker sigma) to H
    $$

    defined by setting $phi (C) = sigma(g)$ for any $g in C$. Here $C$ is a coset of the kernel of $sigma$ and the value of $phi$ is independent of the choice of $g in C$.



    When $sigma$ is not surjective this defines a canonical injective homomorphism.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      I agree with your example, but could you say a sentence or two about what you see in it as being canonical? Why is that particular map the one to choose?
      $endgroup$
      – Santana Afton
      11 hours ago










    • $begingroup$
      @SantanaAfton The map is an integral part of the definition of quotient (or cokernel), hence canonical (given $sigma$)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago
















    3












    3








    3





    $begingroup$

    I agree with @MatthewLeingang that this is an excellent question. A canonical isomorphism is one that comes along with the structures you are investigating, requiring no arbitrary choices. Here's another example from abstract algebra.



    Whenever you have a surjective group homomorphism $sigma: G to H$ there is a natural isomorphism
    $$
    phi : G/(ker sigma) to H
    $$

    defined by setting $phi (C) = sigma(g)$ for any $g in C$. Here $C$ is a coset of the kernel of $sigma$ and the value of $phi$ is independent of the choice of $g in C$.



    When $sigma$ is not surjective this defines a canonical injective homomorphism.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    I agree with @MatthewLeingang that this is an excellent question. A canonical isomorphism is one that comes along with the structures you are investigating, requiring no arbitrary choices. Here's another example from abstract algebra.



    Whenever you have a surjective group homomorphism $sigma: G to H$ there is a natural isomorphism
    $$
    phi : G/(ker sigma) to H
    $$

    defined by setting $phi (C) = sigma(g)$ for any $g in C$. Here $C$ is a coset of the kernel of $sigma$ and the value of $phi$ is independent of the choice of $g in C$.



    When $sigma$ is not surjective this defines a canonical injective homomorphism.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered 17 hours ago









    Ethan BolkerEthan Bolker

    46.9k555123




    46.9k555123












    • $begingroup$
      I agree with your example, but could you say a sentence or two about what you see in it as being canonical? Why is that particular map the one to choose?
      $endgroup$
      – Santana Afton
      11 hours ago










    • $begingroup$
      @SantanaAfton The map is an integral part of the definition of quotient (or cokernel), hence canonical (given $sigma$)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago




















    • $begingroup$
      I agree with your example, but could you say a sentence or two about what you see in it as being canonical? Why is that particular map the one to choose?
      $endgroup$
      – Santana Afton
      11 hours ago










    • $begingroup$
      @SantanaAfton The map is an integral part of the definition of quotient (or cokernel), hence canonical (given $sigma$)
      $endgroup$
      – Hagen von Eitzen
      10 hours ago


















    $begingroup$
    I agree with your example, but could you say a sentence or two about what you see in it as being canonical? Why is that particular map the one to choose?
    $endgroup$
    – Santana Afton
    11 hours ago




    $begingroup$
    I agree with your example, but could you say a sentence or two about what you see in it as being canonical? Why is that particular map the one to choose?
    $endgroup$
    – Santana Afton
    11 hours ago












    $begingroup$
    @SantanaAfton The map is an integral part of the definition of quotient (or cokernel), hence canonical (given $sigma$)
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    10 hours ago






    $begingroup$
    @SantanaAfton The map is an integral part of the definition of quotient (or cokernel), hence canonical (given $sigma$)
    $endgroup$
    – Hagen von Eitzen
    10 hours ago













    0












    $begingroup$

    Too much for a comment, but there some things I do not see mentioned in the existing answers and comments. "Natural" and "canonical" have related but somewhat different meanings in mathematics. This doesn't mean everyone uses them perfectly in accordance to those meanings. But this is a common usage. I'll start out with "natural" first, then bring in "canonical".



    The term natural actually has a precise mathematical meaning, defined in Category theory. In fact, Category theory was originally invented to define what "natural" means. (The first step to studying something is to define it, and once you've defined "natural transformations", you can use them to define "natural" more broadly.)



    An intuitive grasp of "natural" is that it means something is definable by the generic properties of objects in the theory under study, rather than by properties of the specific objects for which the thing is being defined.



    As Matthew Leingang has discussed, finite dimensional real vector spaces are isomorphic to their dual spaces. But in order to have such an isomophism, we have to pick a basis for the vector space. The isomorphism requires something specific to this vector space in order to define it. But we don't require that to define this isomorphism $phi$ of a vector space with its second dual. We can define just from the definition of "dual of a real vector space": $$forall v in V, f in V^*, phi(v)(f) := f(v)$$
    That is why $phi$ is "natural".



    But note this weasel wording in the description above: "in the theory under study". This is why "natural" becomes a word of art, rather than of precision: most of the time, we don't bother to lay out the category that allows a precise definition of "natural". That is left to our audience to deduce. You see, a little tightening of the category under discussion will suddenly turn the unnatural into natural. In finite-dimensional linear algebra, $V$ is not naturally isomorphic to $V^*$. But in the theory of matrices, a column space is naturally isomorphic to a row space by transposing, even though the row space is natually isomorphic to the dual of the column space.



    When someone calls something "natural", you have to figure out in what context they are speaking. And this is where "canonical" comes in. When we call something "canonical" when there is a familiar (and obvious) context where it is natural, but we are (usually) working in a broader context where it is not natural. For example, the canonical basis of $Bbb R^n$ is natural when discussing matrices and column spaces - so natural we don't even mention it, even though it underlies practically everything we do. But if we are considering $Bbb R^n$ as an example of a vector space, then it is not natural, but is defined by non-vector-space properties of $Bbb R^n$. So we use "canonical" to describe it instead.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      0












      $begingroup$

      Too much for a comment, but there some things I do not see mentioned in the existing answers and comments. "Natural" and "canonical" have related but somewhat different meanings in mathematics. This doesn't mean everyone uses them perfectly in accordance to those meanings. But this is a common usage. I'll start out with "natural" first, then bring in "canonical".



      The term natural actually has a precise mathematical meaning, defined in Category theory. In fact, Category theory was originally invented to define what "natural" means. (The first step to studying something is to define it, and once you've defined "natural transformations", you can use them to define "natural" more broadly.)



      An intuitive grasp of "natural" is that it means something is definable by the generic properties of objects in the theory under study, rather than by properties of the specific objects for which the thing is being defined.



      As Matthew Leingang has discussed, finite dimensional real vector spaces are isomorphic to their dual spaces. But in order to have such an isomophism, we have to pick a basis for the vector space. The isomorphism requires something specific to this vector space in order to define it. But we don't require that to define this isomorphism $phi$ of a vector space with its second dual. We can define just from the definition of "dual of a real vector space": $$forall v in V, f in V^*, phi(v)(f) := f(v)$$
      That is why $phi$ is "natural".



      But note this weasel wording in the description above: "in the theory under study". This is why "natural" becomes a word of art, rather than of precision: most of the time, we don't bother to lay out the category that allows a precise definition of "natural". That is left to our audience to deduce. You see, a little tightening of the category under discussion will suddenly turn the unnatural into natural. In finite-dimensional linear algebra, $V$ is not naturally isomorphic to $V^*$. But in the theory of matrices, a column space is naturally isomorphic to a row space by transposing, even though the row space is natually isomorphic to the dual of the column space.



      When someone calls something "natural", you have to figure out in what context they are speaking. And this is where "canonical" comes in. When we call something "canonical" when there is a familiar (and obvious) context where it is natural, but we are (usually) working in a broader context where it is not natural. For example, the canonical basis of $Bbb R^n$ is natural when discussing matrices and column spaces - so natural we don't even mention it, even though it underlies practically everything we do. But if we are considering $Bbb R^n$ as an example of a vector space, then it is not natural, but is defined by non-vector-space properties of $Bbb R^n$. So we use "canonical" to describe it instead.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        0












        0








        0





        $begingroup$

        Too much for a comment, but there some things I do not see mentioned in the existing answers and comments. "Natural" and "canonical" have related but somewhat different meanings in mathematics. This doesn't mean everyone uses them perfectly in accordance to those meanings. But this is a common usage. I'll start out with "natural" first, then bring in "canonical".



        The term natural actually has a precise mathematical meaning, defined in Category theory. In fact, Category theory was originally invented to define what "natural" means. (The first step to studying something is to define it, and once you've defined "natural transformations", you can use them to define "natural" more broadly.)



        An intuitive grasp of "natural" is that it means something is definable by the generic properties of objects in the theory under study, rather than by properties of the specific objects for which the thing is being defined.



        As Matthew Leingang has discussed, finite dimensional real vector spaces are isomorphic to their dual spaces. But in order to have such an isomophism, we have to pick a basis for the vector space. The isomorphism requires something specific to this vector space in order to define it. But we don't require that to define this isomorphism $phi$ of a vector space with its second dual. We can define just from the definition of "dual of a real vector space": $$forall v in V, f in V^*, phi(v)(f) := f(v)$$
        That is why $phi$ is "natural".



        But note this weasel wording in the description above: "in the theory under study". This is why "natural" becomes a word of art, rather than of precision: most of the time, we don't bother to lay out the category that allows a precise definition of "natural". That is left to our audience to deduce. You see, a little tightening of the category under discussion will suddenly turn the unnatural into natural. In finite-dimensional linear algebra, $V$ is not naturally isomorphic to $V^*$. But in the theory of matrices, a column space is naturally isomorphic to a row space by transposing, even though the row space is natually isomorphic to the dual of the column space.



        When someone calls something "natural", you have to figure out in what context they are speaking. And this is where "canonical" comes in. When we call something "canonical" when there is a familiar (and obvious) context where it is natural, but we are (usually) working in a broader context where it is not natural. For example, the canonical basis of $Bbb R^n$ is natural when discussing matrices and column spaces - so natural we don't even mention it, even though it underlies practically everything we do. But if we are considering $Bbb R^n$ as an example of a vector space, then it is not natural, but is defined by non-vector-space properties of $Bbb R^n$. So we use "canonical" to describe it instead.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        Too much for a comment, but there some things I do not see mentioned in the existing answers and comments. "Natural" and "canonical" have related but somewhat different meanings in mathematics. This doesn't mean everyone uses them perfectly in accordance to those meanings. But this is a common usage. I'll start out with "natural" first, then bring in "canonical".



        The term natural actually has a precise mathematical meaning, defined in Category theory. In fact, Category theory was originally invented to define what "natural" means. (The first step to studying something is to define it, and once you've defined "natural transformations", you can use them to define "natural" more broadly.)



        An intuitive grasp of "natural" is that it means something is definable by the generic properties of objects in the theory under study, rather than by properties of the specific objects for which the thing is being defined.



        As Matthew Leingang has discussed, finite dimensional real vector spaces are isomorphic to their dual spaces. But in order to have such an isomophism, we have to pick a basis for the vector space. The isomorphism requires something specific to this vector space in order to define it. But we don't require that to define this isomorphism $phi$ of a vector space with its second dual. We can define just from the definition of "dual of a real vector space": $$forall v in V, f in V^*, phi(v)(f) := f(v)$$
        That is why $phi$ is "natural".



        But note this weasel wording in the description above: "in the theory under study". This is why "natural" becomes a word of art, rather than of precision: most of the time, we don't bother to lay out the category that allows a precise definition of "natural". That is left to our audience to deduce. You see, a little tightening of the category under discussion will suddenly turn the unnatural into natural. In finite-dimensional linear algebra, $V$ is not naturally isomorphic to $V^*$. But in the theory of matrices, a column space is naturally isomorphic to a row space by transposing, even though the row space is natually isomorphic to the dual of the column space.



        When someone calls something "natural", you have to figure out in what context they are speaking. And this is where "canonical" comes in. When we call something "canonical" when there is a familiar (and obvious) context where it is natural, but we are (usually) working in a broader context where it is not natural. For example, the canonical basis of $Bbb R^n$ is natural when discussing matrices and column spaces - so natural we don't even mention it, even though it underlies practically everything we do. But if we are considering $Bbb R^n$ as an example of a vector space, then it is not natural, but is defined by non-vector-space properties of $Bbb R^n$. So we use "canonical" to describe it instead.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered 5 hours ago









        Paul SinclairPaul Sinclair

        21k21543




        21k21543






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3203028%2fbasic-difference-between-canonical-isomorphism-and-isomorphims%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Why do type traits not work with types in namespace scope?What are POD types in C++?Why can templates only be...

            Will tsunami waves travel forever if there was no land?Why do tsunami waves begin with the water flowing away...

            Simple Scan not detecting my scanner (Brother DCP-7055W)Brother MFC-L2700DW printer can print, can't...